This week’s game theory was dedicated to introduction, overview, uses of game theory, some applications and examples, and formal definitions of: the normal form, payoffs, strategies, pure strategy Nash equilibrium, dominant strategies..

Define a Game

  1. Normal form: List what payoffs get as a function of their actions.
  2. Extensive form: Includes timing of moves, players moves sequentially, represented as a tree.

Finite, n-person normal form game: $<n, a,=”” u=””>$:</n,>

  • Players: $N={1, \ldots, n}$, indexed by i;
  • Action set for player i: $a=(a_1, \ldots, a_n) \in A = A_1 \times \ldots \times A_n$ is an action profile;
  • Utility function or Payoff function for player i: $u_i:A \mapsto \mathbf{R} $, $u=(u_1, \ldots, u_n)$ is a profile of utility functions.

Type of Games

Type of Game Properties Examples
Pure Competition 1. Exactly two players of opposed interests; Zero sum special case when $u_1(a)+u_2(a)=0$ Matching Pennies, Rock-Paper-Scissors
Coordination Players have same interests: $\forall a \in A, \forall i,j, u_i(a)=u_j(a)$ side of road
Coordination and Competition Battle of the Sexes

Nash Equilibrium

In game theory, the Nash equilibrium is a solution concept of a non-cooperative game involving two or more players, in which each player is assumed to know the equilibrium strategies of the other players, and no player has anything to gain by changing only their own strategy. If each player has chosen a strategy and no player can benefit by changing strategies while the other players keep theirs unchanged, then the current set of strategy choices and the corresponding payoffs constitute a Nash equilibrium.[^1]

Someone has an incentive to deviate from a profile of actions that do not form an equilibrium.

Best Resopnse
: If you knew what everyone else was going to do, it would be easy to pick your own action.
Nash equilibrium looks for stable action profiles.

Dominant Strategies

Strategy (currently) is choosing an action (“pure strategy”)

Denote $s_i$ and $s_i’$ as two strategies for player i, and $S_{-i}$ be the set of all possible strategy profiles for the other players.

$s_i$ strictly dominates $s_i’$ if $ \forall s_{-i} \in S_{-i}, u_{i}(s_i, s_{-i}) \gt u_{i}(s_i’, s_{-i})$
$s_i$ very weakly dominates $s_i’$ if $ \forall s_{-i} \in S_{-i}, u_{i}(s_i, s_{-i} ) \ge u_{i}(s_i’, s_{-i})$
Please pay attention to the difference between best response, which lies in the definition of strategy.

A strategy profile consisting of dominant strategies for every player must be a Nash equilibrium! An equilibrium in strictly dominant strategies must be unique.

Pareto Optimality

Some times, one outcome $o$ is at least as good for every agent as another outcome $o’$, and there’s some agent who strictly prefers $o$ to $o’$.

An outcome $o^*$ is Pareto-optimal if there is no other outcome that Pareto-dominates it.

[^1]: Nash equilibrium, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Real_number


留言